If i were to attempt to answer this question, i would look first to a deficiency in disciplined rational thinking able to force an objective viewpoint on the self.
The whole architecture of a rational morality has been constructed painstakingly over the past centuries. That it needed to be done surely argues that it is not naturally won. In facyt is is easliy said that good behavior is rather unnatural.
Thus we learn that good behavior is a learned process as amazingly is love itself as against lust and raw attachment. Philosophical love is driven by the rational practice of forgiveness and goes hand in hand.
We do not learn how to respond physically to an attractive member of the opposite sex. We are wired to respond. I do think though that we can learn to transition that natural power in unwanted directions and lose the governors in the process. I base that on the known fact that this does not happen with other creatures provided the right conditions are provided. It is clearly anomalous and actually unnatural.
I do suspect that evil is linked to our built in wiring that operates around the natural community which is actually primitive inasmuch as it handles around 150 relationships. Leadership within that community is naturally accepted and even deferred to in terms of personal decisions. If the leader is weak minded it is easy to have bad results.
Our mental independence actually operates inside the natural rule of twelve which is much more compact. Break out of that and we naturally submit to the natural community which can easily be a mob..
..
.
How evil happens
Why some people choose to do evil remains a puzzle, but are we starting to understand how this behaviour is triggered
https://aeon.co/essays/is-neuroscience-getting-closer-to-explaining-evil-behaviour?
n 1941, en route from a ghetto to a concentration camp in
Ukraine, a Nazi soldier beat my grandfather to death. My father
witnessed this murder. His is just one of millions of similar stories,
of course, and I grew up aware of how death hovered on the other side of
life, and brutality on the underside of humanity. The ‘sapiens’ in Homo sapiens does not fully describe our species: we are as violent as we are smart. This might be why we are the only Homo
genus left over in the first place, and why we have been so
destructively successful at dominating our planet. But still the
question nags away: how are ordinary people capable of such obscene acts
of violence?
This duality is also a puzzle to ourselves, at the
heart of cosmologies, theologies and tragedies, the motor of moral codes
and the tension at the heart of socio-political systems. We know light
and we know dark. We are capable of doing terrible things, but also of
asking ourselves contemplatively and creatively how that is. The
self-consciousness that characterises the human mind is nowhere more
baffling than in this problem of evil, which philosophers have been
discussing since Plato. An obvious place to look for explanations of
evil is in the patterns of behaviour that those who commit atrocities
display.
3
This is what the neurosurgeon Itzhak Fried at the University of California, Los Angeles did with his article ‘Syndrome E’ (1997) in The Lancet.
A syndrome is a group of biological symptoms that together constitute a
clinical picture. And E stands for evil. With Syndrome E, Fried
identified a cluster of 10 neuropsychological symptoms that are often
present when evil acts are committed – when, as he puts it, ‘groups of
previously nonviolent individuals’ turn ‘into repetitive killers of
defenceless members of society’. The 10 neuropsychological symptoms are:
1. Repetition: the aggression is repeated compulsively.
2. Obsessive ideation: the perpetrators are obsessed with ideas that justify their aggression and underlie missions of ethnic cleansing, for instance that all Westerners, or all Muslims, or all Jews, or all Tutsis are evil.
3. Perseveration: circumstances have no impact on the perpetrator’s behaviour, who perseveres even if the action is self-destructive.
4. Diminished affective reactivity: the perpetrator has no emotional affect.
5. Hyperarousal: the elation experienced by the perpetrator is a high induced by repetition, and a function of the number of victims.
6. Intact language, memory and problem-solving skills: the syndrome has no impact on higher cognitive abilities.
7. Rapid habituation: the perpetrator becomes desensitised to the violence.
8. Compartmentalisation: the violence can take place in parallel to an ordinary, affectionate family life.
9. Environmental dependency: the context, especially identification with a group and obedience to an authority, determines what actions are possible.
10. Group contagion: belonging to the group enables the action, each member mapping his behaviour on the other. Fried’s assumption was that all these ways of behaving had underlying neurophysiological causes that were worth investigating.
Note
that the syndrome applies to those previously normal individuals who
become able to kill. It excludes the wartime, sanctioned killing by and
of military recruits that leads many soldiers to return home (if they
ever do) with post-traumatic stress disorder (PTSD); recognised
psychopathologies such as sociopathic personality disorder that can lead
someone to shoot schoolchildren; and crimes of passion or the sadistic
pleasure in inflicting pain. When Hannah Arendt coined her expression
‘the banality of evil’ in Eichmann in Jerusalem (1963), she
meant that the people responsible for actions that led to mass murder
can be ordinary, obeying orders for banal reasons, such as not losing
their jobs. The very notion of ordinariness was tested by social
psychologists. In 1971, the prison experiment by the psychologist Philip
Zimbardo at Stanford University played with this notion that ‘ordinary
students’ could turn into abusive mock ‘prison guards’ – though it was
largely unfounded, given evidence
of flaws in the never-replicated experiment. Still, those afflicted
with Syndrome E are indeed ordinary insofar as that they are not
affected by any evident psychopathology. The historian Christopher
Browning wrote of equally ‘ordinary men’ in the 1992 book of that name
(referenced by Fried) who became Nazi soldiers. The soldier who killed
my grandfather was very probably an ordinary man too.
Today,
biology is a powerful explanatory force for much human behaviour, though
it alone cannot account for horror. Much as the neurosciences are an
exciting new tool for human self-understanding, they will not explain
away our brutishness. Causal accounts of the destruction that humans
inflict on each other are best provided by political history – not
science, nor metaphysics. The past century alone is heavy with
atrocities of unfathomable scale, albeit fathomable political genesis.
But it was the advent of ISIS and the surge in youthful, enthusiastic
recruits to it that gave Fried’s hypothesis a new urgency, and prompted
him to organise, with the neurophysiologist Alain Berthoz at the Collège
de France in Paris, three conferences
around Syndrome E that between 2015 and 2017 gathered cognitive
neuroscientists, social psychologists, neurophysiologists,
psychiatrists, terrorism specialists and jurists, some of whose theories
and insights I share here. Syndrome E is a useful provocation to an
innovative, interdisciplinary discussion of this old problem – and a
powerful example of how to frame neuroscientific output in human terms.
Already this approach is giving rise to interesting hypotheses and
explanations.
As the brain’s functional
anatomy reveals itself in increasingly precise ways, neuroscience is
growing in its ability to address the complexities underlying our
behaviour, violence included. But since we are evolved animals, to
investigate the biological bases for behaviour is to look both at the
embodied results of evolutionary time and at historical time – at how
the evolved circuits of the brain are recruited by cultures, as well as
producing cultures. Given that we evolved as inherently social,
interactive creatures, neuroscience requires dialogue with other
disciplines – the brain has not evolved in isolation, and action always
takes place at a moment in time in a particular place with particular
meaning. The psychological and cultural environment is central in
determining whether and how given biological processes will play out.
The traits enumerated by Fried thus encompass a combination of
neurological and environmental conditions.
Central to Syndrome E
is the symptom of ‘diminished affect’. Most people – except, precisely,
psychopaths – shy away from or are extremely reluctant to inflict pain,
let alone kill. As the psychiatrist Robert Jay Lifton has shown,
it takes brainwashing and coercion to dull our emotional response and
to overcome our reticence to cross the line beyond which ‘habituation’
sets in – the Syndrome E symptom whereby the repetition of the act makes
it easier to perform. Perpetrators of mass murder and torturers can
also love and want the best for their children, while feeling nothing
for their victims – an instance of the ‘compartmentalisation’ symptom of
Syndrome E. This was probably the case for the anonymous Nazi soldier
who killed my grandfather. Family belonging and social belonging are
separate. When they meet, as happened in Bosnia and Rwanda when families
turned on each other, the group identity prevails. Empathy is rarely
universal.
The social neuroscientist Tania Singer at the Max Planck Institute in Leipzig in Germany defines
empathy as the ability to ‘resonate’ with the feelings of the other. It
develops from babyhood on – as imitation at first, then joint attention
– into the ability to adopt the point of view of another, along with a
shift in spatial perception from self to other, as if one were literally
stepping into another’s shoes. This requires an ability to distinguish
between self and other in the first place, an aspect of the so-called
‘theory of mind’ that one acquires over the first five years of life.
The developmental psychologist Philippe Rochat at Emory University in
Atlanta has shown how children develop an ethical stance by that time as well, and become aware of how their actions can be perceived by others.
But
while empathy ensures the cohesion of a group or a society, it is also
biased and parochial. Revenge thrives on it. The social psychologist
Emile Bruneau at the University of Pennsylvania has demonstrated
how it is easily directed at an ‘in-group’ at the expense of an
‘out-group’ that can then be targeted as an enemy, and dehumanised. Its
selectivity also explains how we can walk by a homeless person without
feeling the need to offer help, or rejoice in nasty gossip about a
disliked absentee. Inevitably, we all practise selective empathy, its
absence manifest in everyday, non-lethal instances of violence that
occur in social and family life, in business and politics. What the
psychologist Simon Baron-Cohen at the University of Cambridge calls
‘empathy erosion’ in The Science of Evil: On Empathy and the Origins of Cruelty
(2011) is therefore not a sufficient ingredient in the outbreak of
extreme violence. But it is a necessary one, opening the way to
discrimination and ultimately genocide. As the social neuroscientist
Jean Decety at the University of Chicago put it, ‘our hypersociality has
a dark side’.
This developmental account can dispel, in part, the
mystery of our two faces – of our ability at once to help each other
and to kill each other, or to argue ourselves into ‘just wars’. In
common with other hominins such as chimpanzees, we have evolved the
capacity to cement relationships, communicate and cooperate with those
in our immediate environment – and also to attack outsiders and members
of other tribes. But our evolved self-consciousness is what defines our
humanity even apart from other hominins. What remains puzzling is our
continued ability to destroy even as we are able to understand ourselves
and to create sophisticated scientific models of our own minds.
Under given circumstances, 70 per cent of a population can take part in crimes as part of a group
Neuroscience
gives an interesting physiological model of the emotion of empathy as a
complex, dynamic process that unites executive, premotor and
sensorimotor functions. It recruits, in particular, the ventromedial
prefrontal cortex (vmPFC) and the orbitofrontal context (OFC), with
which the vmPFC overlaps in part, and which is crucial for the
processing of emotions generated in the amygdala – an evolutionary
ancient structure within the limbic system. Lesion to the OFC impairs
emotional feeling – and with it, decision-making. With his ‘somatic
marker hypothesis’,
the neuroscientist Antonio Damasio at the University of Southern
California in Los Angeles has shown how bodily feelings that participate
in signalling emotions, processed in the OFC and vmPFC, enable
appropriate, socially situated decision-making, thereby informing our
evaluations of the world, including our moral sense.
In the
phenomenon of diminished affect, hyperactivity in these same areas of
the frontal lobe inhibits activation of the amygdala. Studies
have shown dysfunctional activity of the OFC in people with
obsessive-compulsive disorder. It thus might also be involved in the
obsessive nature of ideas about one group that justify murderous intent
against its members. And the sense of elated hyperarousal – such as that
induced by cocaine – that entrains action upon these ideas involves
processing in the medial prefrontal cortex (mPFC). In short, in cases of
Syndrome E emotional pathways in the brain no longer regulate judgment
and action. A breakdown occurs in the feedback between the amygdala and
higher, cognitive cortical structures. The acting self splits away from
the feeling self, a phenomenon that Fried calls ‘cognitive fracture’. He
believes that, under given circumstances, about 70 per cent of the
population can be subject to it and be able to take part in crimes as
part of a group – as might have happened in the Stanford prison
experiment, despite caveats regarding its results.
The acting self
of the individual with cognitive fracture feels no empathy. But empathy
is not always a reliable guide to appropriate behaviour – we don’t feel
empathy for the insects dying because of climate change, for instance,
but we can decide rationally to act against the disaster. It can even
lead to bad decisions with regard to those at whom it is directed – a
surgeon who feels empathy for the patient under drapes should really not
operate. There is such a thing as a surfeit of feeling. The
psychologist Paul Bloom at Yale University has argued ‘against empathy’,
in a 2016 book of that title and elsewhere, suggesting that ‘rational
compassion’ is a better barometer with which to evaluate our environment
and how we should act upon it. That is to say, members of a group whose
mission is to kill its perceived enemies might have the ability for
emotional empathy for their group, and no rational compassion for their
perceived enemy.
An account of the
inability to feel any emotion for such perceived enemies can take us
closer to understanding what it is like to have crossed the line beyond
which one can maim and kill in cold blood. Observers at the
International Criminal Court (ICC) at the Hague note frequently the
absence of remorse displayed by perpetrators. The clinical psychologist
Françoise Sironi, who assesses perpetrators for the ICC and treats them
and their victims, has directly seen what Lifton called the ‘murder of
the self’ at work – notably with Kang Kek Iew, the man known as ‘Duch’,
who proudly created and directed the Khmer Rouge S-21 centre for torture
and extermination in Cambodia. Duch was one of those who felt
absolutely no remorse. His sole identity was his role, dutifully kept up
for fear of losing himself and falling into impotence. He did not
comprehend what Sironi meant when she asked him: ‘What happened to your
conscience?’ The very question was gibberish to him.
Along with
what Fried calls this ‘catastrophic’ desensitisation to emotional cues,
cognitive functions remain intact – another Syndrome E symptom. A
torturer knows exactly how to hurt, in full recognition of the victim’s
pain. He – usually he – has the cognitive capacity, necessary but not
sufficient for empathy, to understand the victim’s experience. He just
does not care about the other’s pain except instrumentally. Further, he
does not care that he does not care. Finally, he does not care that
caring does, in fact, matter. The emotionally inflected judgment that
underlies the moral sense is gone.
Such a state involves the
fusion of identity with a larger system within which occurs the
splitting of the feeling self and the cognitive self, and the
concomitant replacement of individual moral values with that system’s
norms and rules. Chemistry is operative throughout, as it is in all
cerebral and somatic functions – and tweakable by pharmaceuticals. The
neuroscientist Trevor Robbins at the University of Cambridge has studied
‘pharmacoterrorism’, and how, for instance, the amphetamine Captagon – used,
inter alia, by ISIS members – affects dopamine function, depletes
serotonin in the OFC, and leads to rigid, psychopathic-like behaviour,
increasing aggression and leading to the perseverance that Fried lists
among the Syndrome E symptoms. It shuts off social attachment, and
disables all emotional feeling (empathy included), a condition called
alexithymia.
This is one simplified neurological account of how
murderous action becomes possible. The neuroscience of value and action
can help to further explain what might be going on. The OFC is
exceptionally developed in humans and primates. As Edmund Rolls at the
Oxford Centre for Computational Neuroscience has shown,
it plays a crucial role in representing reward value in response to a
stimulus: we make choices based on the assignation of value – to an
object, an idea, an action, a norm, a person. Our emotions are
value-rich, and our actions vary and can be updated according to how
they are met in the world, in turn motivating us to seek or avoid a
stimulus. Our behaviour can continue in the search of an absent reward –
this would be one account of compulsive action, a Syndrome E symptom.
The neuroscientist Mathias Pessiglione and his team in Paris have also shown
a central role for vmPFC in value-attribution to a stimulus or an idea,
whereby we choose to undertake an action based on its attractive reward
or its aversive outcome. But when this function is overstimulated, new
inputs – such as cries for mercy – have no impact on the attribution of
value to the idea, for instance that ‘all you people deserve to die’,
and action cannot change. It becomes automatic, controllable by an
external agent or leader, independently of any sense of value.
Coercion switches off the sense of responsibility – a chilling finding
But
these neurological events signify criminal action only under particular
environmental circumstances. The psychiatrist David Cohen and his team
at the Pitié-Salpêtrière hospital in Paris evaluated teenage candidates
for radicalisation. They found that certain socio-psychological
conditions in childhood – such as an absent father or an unstable
mother, and a history of foster care – affected the development of
identity, in some cases eventually leading to the need to subsume it
into a wider group with a transcendental message. Again, group trumps
family. As the anthropologist Scott Atran has shown,
conflicts are often intractable and non-negotiable because they are
conducted in the name of absolute, spiritual values – secular or
religious – and not for any utilitarian outcome. These values can seem
highly attractive – stronger than family ties.
In her novel Home Fire
(2017), the British Pakistani writer Kamila Shamsie showed how a
loving, innocent but maladjusted and lost young man of Pakistani origin
could fall prey to an ISIS recruiter’s siren call to rejoin a lost
father and find fulfilment and belonging in a community depicted as
devoted to a greater good. Our narratives, inner and outer, inform and
justify the choices we make, conferring on them a coherence that is
reassuring and can seem good and right. Coherence rides on the moral
sense and masquerades as it, bringing on a cognitive dissonance ‘between
what we think and what we do’, as Zimbardo once put it – between what
we convince ourselves was an appropriate action, and our deeply held,
prior beliefs. Shamsie’s character soon regrets his choice and tries to
get away from a violence he cannot stomach, unable to withstand the
cognitive dissonance. Not so Nazi doctors, say, who convinced themselves
that they were acting for a greater good – in a perverse twist to the
equivalence of morality with a concern for the good of others. Heinrich
Himmler’s speech in Poznan in 1943 is a chilling instance of this
high-minded justification of criminal behaviour: ‘We have the moral
right, we had the duty to our people to do it, to kill this people who
wanted to kill us.’ Once moral justification is divorced from an
emotionally calibrated response to the other, violence can be deployed
on rationalised grounds. This has happened time and again throughout
history.
But ‘ordinary men’ must cross a line into that zone where
the Syndrome E symptoms operate – pushed by circumstance. A noteworthy
insight into what happens during the crossing is provided by the
neuroscientist Patrick Haggard at University College London. He has
shown how powerful is the initial coercion that allows us to step beyond
the line. In the wake of the 1961 trial in Jerusalem of Adolf Eichmann,
who invoked the ‘Nuremberg Defence’ that he was ‘just obeying orders’ –
so-called because it was first used by the Nazi defendants in the
Nuremberg Trials of 1945-46 – the psychologist Stanley Milgram at Yale
University showed, or rather exaggeratedly claimed, that most people
will obey orders from an authority even if the order is to harm another
person. Milgram was interested in obedience. Haggard, who has been studying
the sense of agency – the sense that we initiate and own our actions,
which is central to our lives, and also to legal arguments about
criminal accountability – asked instead what it feels like to be coerced
and have one’s autonomy removed to some degree. Through an experiment
that partly takes its cue from Milgram’s (but addresses some of its
ethical and methodological issues) and uses the intentional binding
effect, Haggard found that people do feel a notable reduction in their
sense of agency when they are coerced into an action. Coercion switches
off the sense of responsibility – a chilling finding.
The
neurological correlates of what can lead to our worst actions do not
indicate a clinical condition. Syndrome E is not a disease, nor quite a
disorder eligible for integration into the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders
or the International Statistical Classification of Diseases and Related
Problems. If it were officialised as such, it would have intricate
juridical ramifications: the use of neurological evidence in court is
problematic, as the jurist Jean-Paul Costa, a former president of the
European Court of Human Rights, has pointed out, because it requires the
expert reading of imprecise and opaque data. It is hard to establish
exactly which brain events – including those underlying the sense of
agency – could or should constitute legally mitigating factors.
But
introducing, as Fried has done, a set of features that characterise our
most beastly nature, and kickstarting a wide-ranging discussion across
the fields relevant to their study, particularly in the area of
neuroscience, can only help to enrich programmes of prevention and
remediation at a time when these are sorely needed. The devil might be
dead, but evil actions will always exist. The ‘Why?’ remains a
metaphysical puzzle, and I am one of the millions whose life is lived
under this question mark, passed on by my survivor father. But at least
some answers to the ‘How?’ are now within our reach.
No comments:
Post a Comment