This is an insightful discussion on the meme of tolerance which certainly has informed western thinking and education for a long time. Our present problem is that this meme is not shared by every prospective immigrant group and accepted once they arrive.
It must become an actual condition for immigration and any one teaching intolerance needs to be subjected to summary censure and if necessary, actual silencing. We do exactly that for hate speech and incitement to criminal behavior. This really not subject to fuzzy thinking except by sophists.
A civil society is based on tolerance This is not about racism either. Random acts of intolerance will often be expressed as a racist slur, but is actually the convenient attack phrase to use against a complete stranger when nothing else is available. Thus our education needs to double down on insuring that we all learn to avoid all form of intolerant language meant to inflame the emotions of the victim.
Calling a women a slut in a moment of anger is high on the list. We have way too many culturally acceptable Pejoratives to not now take stock of the content of our language and to teach other ways of expressing anger verbally. ..
.
What is wrong with tolerance
The ideal of religious tolerance has crippling flaws. It’s time to embrace a civic philosophy of reciprocity
https://aeon.co/essays/reciprocity-not-tolerance-is-the-basis-of-healthy-societies?
The purpose of religious tolerance has always been, and remains, to
maintain the power and purity of the dominant religion in a given state.
Most dominant religions in most states today profess tolerance, but
they also seem to feel especially threatened. Religious nationalist
movements in the United States, Europe, India, Turkey and Israel all
want to strengthen the relationship between state identity and the
dominant religion. In each case, democratic elections have reinforced
the significance of the majority’s religion to the meaning of state and
nation, elevating the power of that religion. We can see a rising
chauvinism in the mix of Catholicism and politics in eastern Europe
today that portrays liberals and communists (often a code for ‘Jews’) as
enemies. We can see a similar dynamic in the Turkish celebration of the
Ottoman conquest of Constantinople in 1453. And we can also see it in
the reemerging influence of Evangelicals in the US, as defenders of
‘religious liberty’ in their associations and businesses, and against
‘Sharia’ – as they imagine it – in the public sphere.
Even as
religious nationalism gains strength, claims to membership in the ‘West’
rest in large part on a political avowal of religious tolerance. When
religious nationalists claim the mantle of tolerance based on the legal
protections that exist for religious minorities in their states, they
are not wrong. Tolerance has indeed historically been a framework for
people fundamentally different from one another to live peacefully
together. Which is precisely why it is time to dispense once and for all
with tolerance as a model for relations between groups.
Tolerance
skepticism has a long history, stretching back to the German author J W
Goethe, who said ‘to tolerate is to insult’. It faced a sustained
critique after the Second World War from philosophers and political
theorists such as Karl Popper, Herbert Marcuse and many others who saw
liberal tolerance as guilty of passively acquiescing to the rise of
fascism in the first half of the 20th century. Where Popper saw that a
liberal society required repression of some intolerant views for
self-preservation, Marcuse saw liberalism’s tolerance of injustice as
the problem itself.
Following Marcuse, in the 1960s the New Left
asked if the idea of tolerance – especially of speech and political
diversity – served only to shield governments, corporations and the
elite in continuing policies of economic and racial oppression. More
recently, a school of international-relations scholarship
has emerged emphasising how the foreign policy guiding Western
governments now divides the world between the tolerant and the
intolerant in much the same way that it has always distinguished between
the civilised (whites) and the barbaric (everyone else). Even so, the
question of how tolerance – religious tolerance in particular – could be
a tool of domination strikes many people as counterintuitive or
perverse. Tolerance is deeply rooted in the canon of apparent modern
ideals: as an inherent good, a necessary individual ethic, a pillar of
Western civilisation and proof of its superiority.
Yet tolerance,
as an idea and an ethic, obscures the interaction between individuals
and groups on both a daily basis and over the longue durée;
the mutually reinforcing exchange of culture and ideas between groups
in a society is missing in the idea of tolerance. Groups do not interact
in isolation, they share reciprocally, sometimes intentionally and
sometimes inadvertently. If it is true that a global society exists,
what its best parts embody today is not tolerance, but reciprocity, the
vital and dynamic relationship of mutual exchange that occurs every day
between individuals and groups within a society. For teachers,
journalists and politicians to begin to speak in terms of reciprocity
instead of tolerance will not do away with intolerance or prejudice. But
words are important and, as much as they reflect our thoughts, they
also shape how we think. Idealising tolerance embeds dominance. Speaking
in terms of reciprocity instead of tolerance would both better reflect
what peaceful societies look like, and also tune people’s minds to the
societal benefits of cultural exchange.
The idea of tolerance owes its origins in part to the Augustinian
tradition of the early Christian Church, which was greatly concerned
with defining the boundaries of the Christian community. How could
Christians live peacefully with people they believed to have crucified
their god? St Augustine’s position on the Jews held that these
crucifiers should be allowed to live in the midst of Christians and to
bear witness to the fate of those who reject Christ. Jews would remain
on the outside of the holy Christian community – tolerated, as a remnant
of the pre-Christian past. But Christian tolerance of Jews also created
a theological problem: how to square the premise of God’s punishment of
the Jews with the simultaneous reality of Jewish agency, sometimes
prosperity, and sometimes power (even over Christians).
To take
one example, during Poland’s late-medieval and early modern expansion,
the need for mobile, literate managers with commercial experience (and
preferably few political demands) led the Polish nobility and the Crown
to welcome Jews to Poland to fulfil important socioeconomic roles. Some
towns in the 14th century wrote charters for the Jews, outlining
explicitly their freedom to organise their autonomous religious and
communal life for the benefit of mutual Jewish and Christian prosperity.
Yet this prosperity also brought increased competition between Jews and
Christian burghers, to whom, by the 16th century, the Crown granted in
some towns the Privilegium de non tolerandis Judaeis (the right
not to tolerate Jews). The town of Lublin received such a privilege in
1535, but then the Jews, who formed a Jewish town at the foot of the
castle walls (on the outside) received a parallel privilege, de non tolerandis Christianis
in 1568. These arrangements successfully created a stable society with
co-dependent and reciprocal relationships between groups, even while the
goal of tolerance for all parties remained the greatest possible
isolation, or perhaps insulation, from one another.
Islam,
Buddhism, Confucianism, Sikhism and many other civilisations have
historically maintained their own traditions of religious tolerance. On
the other hand, Europe’s Reformations, if anything, expanded
intolerance. The Reformation made stamping out heresy a marker of
religious devotion. Before the compromises required for different
Christians to live among one another were made, violent religious wars
plagued Europe for 100-plus years in the wake of the Protestant and
Catholic reformations (from the mid-16th to the mid-17th century). Legal
tolerance might have been the winning solution to resolve that
century-long descent into fratricide but, for a long time after the
reformations, intolerance was seen as a worthwhile theological
attribute. A Christian refusal to tolerate significant deviation from
doctrinal orthodoxy – or the Jew or the Muslim, or the ‘heathens’ and
‘savages’ whom Europeans were first encountering in their Age of
Discovery – was a marker of holiness and purity, and of a leader’s
willingness to put spiritual matters above earthly concerns. A certain
notion of tolerance, and the necessity of freedom of conscience in
places where the balance of military power was not held overwhelmingly
by one group or another, did indeed grow from the reformations and the
wars of religion. But it took many years, with dramatic downs and ups,
for the idea of tolerance to become a positive good valued in European
society.
Tolerance was not a virtue brought to America: it was imposed by Europe to administer its overseas empires
For
the first English theorists of tolerance such as John Locke, tolerance
was necessary first and foremost to protect Christianity and Christians’
souls. As Locke put it, ‘that I esteem that toleration to be the chief
characteristic mark of the true Church’ (some have tried to
differentiate between tolerance and toleration – using the latter to
refer to state policy – but the two words remain synonymous in common
usage). It was in the 17th century, at the very earliest, that the idea
of tolerance began to take root in Europe as a principle consistent with
good and effective government, and only with the European Enlightenment
in the 17th and 18th centuries that philosophers, theologians,
political theorists and men of letters argued that tolerating difference
was necessary for a functioning and prosperous society. The idea of a
citizen or subject’s ‘right to toleration’ circulated throughout Europe
with the philosophes’ project of the Encyclopédie
(1751-72), an attempt to reorganise human knowledge in a way that its
editor Denis Diderot believed would ‘change the general way of
thinking’. Not only republicans, but enlightened absolutists too, such
as Prussia’s Frederick the Great and the Holy Roman Emperor Joseph II,
became proponents of tolerance, always, of course, defined on their own
terms.
It was in the American colonies where European powers –
first the Dutch and then the British, seeking peace among their
colonists – instituted protection of individual religious conscience.
Contrary to American national mythology, tolerance was not a distinct
virtue carried to America by those who built their imagined city upon a
hill: it was imposed by European colonial powers
to better administer their overseas empires. The ideal of religious
tolerance was sewn further in the colonies by transplanted Londoners
such as William Penn and Roger Williams, but always to protect
Christianity from politics, and not the other way around.
The US,
from its birth, marked groups for tolerance and intolerance. The country
attempted to conquer, control and Christianise the native people and,
until the Indian Citizenship Act of 1924, the very minimum tolerance –
the simple ability to live – was denied to them in most places, and in
others was the most they received. Africans fell into an entirely
different category; slavery reflects neither tolerance nor intolerance,
but rather inhumanity. Even so, the idea that the foundation of the
American polity is a multiplicity of ideals – religious and political –
was a tension among the founders of the early republic who themselves
debated which Enlightenment principles should stand at the forefront of
their ideological experiment. It was Thomas Jefferson and James
Madison’s vision that an enlightened state must resist creating a
religious foundation upon which other dissenting views are dependent for
toleration. Jefferson’s view of the political community failed to
include women, African Americans or native people, but he grasped the
danger of premising citizenship on the tolerance of one religious group
by another.
The Enlightenment, the
rise of nation states, two world wars and post-war European
decolonisation transformed tolerance from a legal concept that regulated
the privileges and disabilities of minority religions to a
philosophical and ethical ideal. With the ascension of international
human rights law following the Second World War, states stopped
articulating the protection of minorities in edicts of tolerance or
guarantees of minority rights. They instead created legal protections
for speech and conscience and laws protecting against discrimination.
Many of the old compromises of early modern toleration live on in state
churches, officially recognised religious minorities and the
accommodations to religion (especially in family law) that remain in
many states. But for the most part, as the political theorist Wendy
Brown has observed in Regulating Aversion
(2008), the sites of tolerance have changed. Tolerance is discussed
today as a moral rather than a legal question, and as a matter of civic
and cultural life rather than as a practical answer to theological
problems.
In fact, tolerance has never escaped its origins as a
means for the majority to regulate the minority. It continues to be the
case that in today’s national state system the overwhelming majority of
governments associate the state directly or indirectly with the majority
religion. This is even true in states with legal neutrality on matters
of religion such as the US and France. As such, tolerance remains a
one-way relationship between the tolerating and the tolerated that,
intended or not, keeps the tolerated outside of full membership in the
dominant group. In contrast to tolerance, reciprocity recognises that
strong and dynamic societies are based on social and cultural exchange.
Pluralism and multiculturalism are variations on toleration, with appreciation for the benefits of diversity
A
focus on reciprocal exchange first emerged in the social philosophy of
the early pluralists of the American intellectual tradition about 100
years ago, who battled nativism and resistance to immigration. For
instance, in 1915 the philosopher Horace Kallen attacked the sociologist
and eugenicist Edward Alsworth Ross for his claim that 20th-century
immigrants to the US brought with them dual allegiances that could not
be assimilated into American society. Kallen argued in the Nation
that what the ‘dominant classes in America’ fear is precisely the fact
that, in the process of becoming American, religious and national groups
create something new and different that in turn affects American
civilisation. Kallen, who coined the term ‘cultural pluralism’ in 1925,
and others among the first theorists of pluralism in the country, argued
against a kind of toleration contingent on groups effacing their
origins. Rather, the pluralism that took hold in some universities and
urban landscapes – and certainly not without resistance – presumed that
the US and its immigrants benefited reciprocally from immigration.
The
early pluralists’ preferred metaphor for American civilisation was a
symphony. In this metaphor, each group contributed a distinct sound to
an evolving and harmonious musical arrangement. But the fact that each
group played its own instrument, and performed from its own music,
became a problem for later critics of both pluralism and
multiculturalism. The symphony is fine and good, so the argument goes,
except when everyone is too concerned with the musicality of their own
performance. For liberal doubters, pluralism’s emphasis on ethnic and
religious identities only serves to draw boundaries that exaggerate
differences. For conservative critics, multiculturalism is incoherent
compared with patriotism to country, the only identity of significance.
Without all groups adopting a shared civic identity, the ideals of
pluralism and multiculturalism are just variations on the old idea of
toleration, albeit with a greater appreciation for the benefits of
diversity to society.
However, using reciprocity as a lens to view
society, the instruments themselves change, and are exchanged, along
with the music. Like pluralism and multiculturalism, reciprocity exalts
the virtuous circle by which the many cultures of groups shape the
culture of a state, and the evolving culture of a state in turn changes
the cultures of the groups. Yet unlike pluralism and multiculturalism,
reciprocity, as a term, directly evokes active mutual interaction and
influence. And as a philosophy, reciprocity recognises the mutual
collective responsibilities, and even sacrifices, necessary for such
symbiosis. All individuals, in our daily choices and conduct, give up
some element of our identities to belong to the broader society. In
Émile Durkheim’s great work The Elementary Forms of Religious Life
(1912), he argued that every individual must transcend his or her own
needs to participate in a society. The ‘collective effervescence’ that
the individual feels in being a member of that community and
participating in its rituals is not only very real, but is the essence
of every religion and society. At the same time, societies and states –
be they civic empires or federations, nation states, ethno-religious
states or something else – need reciprocity to thrive. History
has left us no examples of civilisations that have flourished without
the exchange of cultures, ideas and people.
What
about those who refuse to acknowledge that reciprocity is the root of
all healthy societies? The question of the limits of toleration has
provided grist for the mill of many political theorists; is reciprocity
vulnerable to the same vexations? If reciprocity’s binary is understood
to be total isolation, then the answer is no. Perhaps one of the
benefits of reciprocity as a philosophy or an individual and collective
ethic is that it is impossible for any group to live in a society, or at
least a liberal-democratic society, non-reciprocally. There are always
individual non-contributors, but no group can exist within a society
without reciprocal exchange. Individuals and groups might see themselves
as living in tolerated isolation, but it is very unlikely that
reciprocal exchange is not going on. If a group was to say we don’t want to behave reciprocally with the state, other groups or society, the response must be that, willingly or not, you
already do. American reciprocity has shaped religious groups extolling
isolation – such as the Amish in Pennsylvania or Hasidim in New York –
no less than anyone else. As for those who claim that they
(being some other group) do not behave reciprocally, the response must
be that reciprocity posits the impossibility of such an existence.
One
of my students astutely pointed out that the problem with reciprocity
is that the mutuality it invokes does not take proper account of the
hierarchies that exist in all societies. How, for example, would
reciprocity resonate with a group that is impoverished and marginalised?
Such a group is unlikely to see its relationship with the dominant
society through the lens of reciprocity. Nonetheless, reciprocity
remains a helpful ideal from which to approach this structural
inequality. Social marginalisation, for example of African Americans in
the US or Muslims in Europe, reflects a breakdown in reciprocity that
can only be improved by greater recognition of the contributions of all
groups to our collective wellbeing. The logic and psychology of
reciprocity suggests that humans feel a sense of obligation to behave
reciprocally toward one another, and that reciprocity is the source of
such basic human activities as the rituals of gift-giving. Similarly,
civic reciprocity already regulates the relationship between states and
groups: the treatment of groups by a state or society tends to determine
the sense of obligation to that state or society among individuals in
those groups.
We can shift away from a binary vocabulary that counters intolerance with calls for tolerance.
Reciprocity
is a philosophy, a social ethic, a way of seeing the world, and a
psychology. At its most basic distillation, it can serve as a
description of both what binds individuals and groups to and within a
society, and the mutual exchange of culture that serves as the lifeblood
of all prosperous societies. Finding a new framework to approach
societal problems is important at a time when ideological differences
resting on economic worldview seem to be fading. Because one set of
ideals (for diversity, pluralism and exchange) is being challenged by
another (for intolerance or, at best, a return to a highly contingent
tolerance), a space has opened for a new civic philosophy.
To
develop the concept of reciprocity as an individual and collective
political ethic we can teach it, study it and write about it. Most of
all, we can talk about it, shifting away from a binary vocabulary that
counters intolerance with calls for tolerance, and toward a discussion
of shared histories and mutual obligations. We must also individually
and as groups acknowledge our own civic responsibilities, to our society
and to one another, as we respect the contributions of others. In the
elected representatives we choose, the policies we support or oppose,
and the causes we take on, we can idealise reciprocity as a positive
good, and measure ourselves and the progress of our societies against
that ideal.
The Constitution of the French Second Republic,
enacted during the wave of democratic revolutions known as the
Springtime of the Peoples, which swept through Europe in 1848, includes
one simple article that grants no right or power to either the state or
the people. Article VI states only:
‘Reciprocal duties bind the citizens to the Republic and the Republic
to the citizens.’ Reciprocity makes this claim but goes further: the
more we acknowledge what reciprocally binds each group to the society,
and the society to each group, the better off we will all be.
This
Essay was made possible through the support of a grant from the
Templeton Religion Trust to Aeon. The opinions expressed in this
publication are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect the
views of the Templeton Religion Trust.
No comments:
Post a Comment