His doctrine of non violence was the culmination of a healthy intellectual life. It was also revolutionary and it has worked over and over again because it produces resistance that cannot be answered properly with force.
He also has much to teach, not least in his progress because he was truly challenged by the world at large and not by an academe.
Far too many try to forget his existence but they are lesser souls.
Gandhi the philosopher
Better known as the face of non-violent protest, Gandhi was also a surprising, subtle philosopher in the Stoic tradition
https://aeon.co/essays/gandhi-was-a-subtle-surprising-philosopher-in-the-stoic-style?
Was Mahatma Gandhi a philosopher? He would not have thought so
himself. But I want to show that he was a model for philosophy in the
philosophical subtlety of his accounts of non-violence and in his thinking on a vital kind of freedom.
Gandhi was full of surprises: in his defence of concrete particularity
in ethics when exceptionless rules cannot guide conduct; in his openness
to views from other cultures; and in his exemplary response to
criticism, which was welcomed, promulgated without being distorted,
treated with disconcerting wit, and used to lead to a radical
re-thinking of his own views.
Of course, Gandhi (1869-1948) is
known for his belief in non-violence, which included, but was by no
means confined to, non-violent resistance to the British rulers of
India. But it is less well-known that he rejected the non-violence he
had heard of in India. Although the most important influence in his life
was the Jain faith, on non-violence, he preferred the second most
important influence – Leo Tolstoy. He thought, rightly or wrongly, that
the Indian view he knew did not sufficiently mind someone else treading
on a beetle, so long as one kept oneself pure by not treading on it
oneself. Gandhi saw his early self as a votary of violence. It was the
Russian Christian writer, Tolstoy, who converted Gandhi to non-violence,
a fact that shows his openness to views from other cultures.
For this openness to views from elsewhere, Gandhi acknowledged the value of another Jain view – that ordinary humans have only partial
knowledge, from which he concluded that truth must be sought in diverse
quarters. He described non-violence as being, on Tolstoy’s view, an
ocean of compassion – one would not want anyone to tread on a beetle. But more than that, you should never hate your opponent. With his permission, Gandhi published Tolstoy’s A Letter to a Hindoo (1909),
which argued that millions of Indians were enslaved to a few thousand
British only because, instead of internalising the law of love, they
cooperated with the British in carrying out the violence on which their
enslavement depended.
Gandhi combined the attitude of compassion to all, opponents included, with a readiness for self-sacrifice
so that, in resisting the British, he was ready to suffer a violent
response without ever hating. But he did not think that all should join
his non-violent confrontations, because everyone has a different
character and hence a different duty (svadharma), since only
some can retain the non-violent attitude in the face of violence. For
those who could not, he set up a ‘constructive programme’, to carry out a
different type of work.
In 1926, Gandhi wrote a series of eight
newspaper articles, including an English version, under the title ‘Is
This Humanity?’, in which he refined his conception of non-violence. In
particular, he addressed the question: when is killing non-violent? This
question was triggered by his support of the head of a municipality,
who had authorised the killing of 60 stray dogs for fear that they might
spread rabies. Outraged letters came to Gandhi from all over India,
saying: ‘We thought you were a man of non-violence.’
Gandhi
offered a model of philosophical reaction. He published a number of the
letters in his newspapers, not concealing, nor misrepresenting, the
criticisms, although he allowed himself a witticism: that one of the
letters demanding non-violence was violent. Nonetheless, Gandhi sought
to rethink his position, in order to provide an answer, and by the end
of the third article offered a new criterion. Killing was always
violent, unless it was done for the sake of the killed. Was that not an
admission that he was in the wrong, since killing the stray dogs was not
for their sake, although it might have been for the sake of other dogs,
and people? But he had already, in the first article, made an important
philosophical point:
A city-dweller who is responsible for the protection of lives under his care … is faced with a conflict of duties. If he kills the dog, he commits a sin. If he does not kill it, he commits a graver sin. So he prefers to commit the lesser one and save himself from the greater.
In other words, it was wrong
to kill the dogs, because one is sometimes, through no fault of one’s
own, in a moral double-bind: wrong if one does and wrong if one doesn’t.
This was known to the ancient Greeks, but resisted for a long time by
Christianity. In the Greek story, Orestes was in a moral double-bind:
wrong if he did not avenge his father by killing the assassin, but wrong
if he killed his mother, who was the assassin. Christianity at first
found this hard to accept, because eternal punishment was expected for
serious wrongdoing and, since God was just, the wrongdoing needed to be
one’s fault. As a result, in the 6th century CE, elaborate attempts were
made to locate a fault. But Gandhi saw that sometimes choosing violence
is not one’s fault. He nonetheless continued to hold that all violence
was wrong, and was not even tempted by the implausibly lenient idea
that, if something is not one’s fault, it can only be apparently wrong, prima facie.
This
in turn meant that although Gandhi admits a few exceptionless moral
principles (in this case, all chosen violence is wrong), he does not
think that exceptionless principles can on their own guide us on conduct – they do not tell us what to do, since we might have personal duties, a svadharma
such as responsibility for municipal welfare, that would make the
non-violent course the worse one for us. Gandhi might think that certain
attitudes, such as non-violence as compassion, are universally
desirable. But even so, he does not aim to alter the attitude, or the
conduct, of those Muslims who believed instead in retaliation.
I sympathise with Gandhi’s denial that exceptionless universal principles can tell us what to do.
In ancient Greece, the later Stoics too after Panaetius (late 2nd
century BCE) were particularists in ethics, but went further in avoiding
exceptionless moral principles. A text based on Panaetius tells us that
when Julius Caesar marched his army on the city of Utica in his bid for
supreme power in Rome, it was right for the Stoic Cato, who was there,
to commit suicide, but not right for anyone else in the same
circumstances, and this was because of Cato’s uniquely uncompromising
character in standing up for the Roman republic. To explain why this was
right only for Cato, one would have to depend on people knowing Cato’s
history, or else illustrate that history. In either case, one would not
have the kind of universal principle that was being looked for, but a
rationale that depended on reference to an individual or to his
particular history – that is, to his unique Stoic persona, or his Gandhian svabhava, and to the resulting personal duty (svadharma).
It
has been said that the ancient Confucians in China avoided universal
ethical principles, and an unfavourable contrast has been drawn with
Western followers of Immanuel Kant and of utilitarianism. Why then does
Gandhi nonetheless keep the universal principle that all violence is
wrong? He has an answer to this too. One reason is that the principle is
a counsel of perfection for the imperfect, which helps us to raise our
sights, even though we cannot altogether avoid choosing violence. It is
not surprising that, looking at Gandhi as simply a politician, many, and
especially the British then, could have thought that he was a political
twister, saying whatever suited him as and when. But if he says at one
time: ‘Don’t use violence,’ and at another time: ‘Do use it,’ this is
actually the product, to my mind, of perceptive philosophical thought.
My
second illustration is Gandhi’s treatment of freedom. There was a long
tradition behind his unusual views on freedom, and Gandhi certainly had
access to some of it, but he might have worked it out for himself, only
sometimes making use of the antecedents. The fullest account was in the
ancient Stoics, starting with Epictetus in the 1st century CE. Gandhi
read a book about three major Stoics, including Epictetus, which he
called inspiring, but only in 1922-24, after many of his views were
already formed. And in 1926 his learned secretary Mahadev Desai
commented that Gandhi’s ideals were sometimes remarkably similar to
Stoic ideals, citing two examples of the different topic of personal
duty.
In Discourse, the Stoic Epictetus presents personal freedom as a kind of invulnerability gained by setting your heart, or rather your will (prohairesis),
only on what it is in your power to have. Then the tyrant cannot do
anything to you. What is in your power does not include your body, its
parts, your faculties, your possessions, your reputation, offices,
honours, children, brothers, friends, farm, slaves, clothes, house or
horses. For thinkers, in case they felt safe, he added ‘your books’.
Epictetus
describes the exercises by which he makes his students set aside any
consideration that is not under the control of their wills. To a tyrant
who threatens: ‘I will put you in chains,’ they are to imagine
themselves replying: ‘What did you say, man? Put me in chains? My leg you will put in chains, but my will
not even God can conquer.’ The students are to learn to be free by
reducing themselves to their wills – that is, to their rightly directed
wills.
Already in 300 BCE, the founder of Stoicism, Zeno from
Cyprus, had said that only the person who has become truly good is
actually free; all who are not good are slaves. Zeno also introduced the
Stoic idea that only good character is really good, although other
things have a certain limited value. It is natural to pursue some things
– food, pleasure, health and life itself – and it is right to follow
nature. But the test comes if we fail to get them. Then what really
matters is whether we exercise good character by pursuing them in the
right way. It is not securing the objectives that really matters. In
Stoic terminology, the objectives are indifferent, but they are
naturally preferred indifferents, which we must pursue for ourselves and
others, if we are to be good people. Similarly, there are naturally
dispreferred indifferents, and having your leg put in chains would
doubtless be an example. But thinking that this is only a rightly
dispreferred indifferent might reinforce Epictetus’ new point that you
should think your leg is not you.
Epictetus finishes his Discourse
on freedom by identifying only two people who were free, both from
Athens in the 4th century BCE: Socrates and Diogenes the Cynic, who
lived in a wine vase, both of whom defied convention and influenced the
Stoics. But there have been modern followers of Epictetus’ ideal of
freedom. In 1993, I invited the US war hero Admiral James Stockdale to
London to discuss with Greek scholars, a psychologist and the general
public how a course on Epictetus he’d taken at university meant that,
years later during the Vietnam War, he welcomed and withstood 19
occasions of physical torture (some exploiting, in Epictetan fashion,
his broken leg) and four years of solitary confinement by his captors.
As the resulting article
and the book written with his wife describe, Stockdale was conducting
what Gandhi would have called an experiment. The deliberate provoking of
punishment by small infractions of the rules in captivity restored his
self-esteem, and that of other captives, whom he similarly persuaded,
which left them all free to refuse the captors’ limited objective of securing televised denunciations of the war.
Whether or not Gandhi knew the Stoic ideas, he knew their prototype from Plato’s Apology
(4th century BCE), of which he wrote a paraphrase in 1908. There
Socrates, is presented as defending himself before a jury against
charges of corrupting the youth by philosophical discussion of
conventional values and by introducing false gods. Plato presents
Socrates as saying that exclusion from office, exile or execution would
not be a harm to him; only his accusers would be harmed by trying to
kill a man unjustly. Like the Stoics later, Socrates here treats justice
as a real good, and the usual objectives as indifferent. However, in
treating unjust treatment as not harming him, he did not go as far as
Epictetus’ admiring description of the true Cynic as someone who loves
those who are beating him as if he were the father or brother of them
all. By bringing in love, Epictetus comes closer to Tolstoy’s Christian
law of love, which so influenced Gandhi.
‘No power on Earth can make a person do a thing against his will’
Gandhi was more directly influenced on freedom, as on non-violence, by Tolstoy. We saw earlier, in A Letter to a Hindoo, the influence of Tolstoy’s view on non-violence, that Indians would be free
from British rule, if they internalised the law of love and stopped
cooperating on violent projects. Tolstoy saw freedom in recognition,
when he said that Indians are enslaved by violence only because they do
not recognise the eternal law of love inherent in humanity. Similarly, in Gandhi’s other favourite work by Tolstoy, The Kingdom of God is Within You (1894), Tolstoy writes that you will be free as soon as you recognise
that the role you play in a violent society is not needed for the
public good. The reference to love, we saw above, was brought into the
Stoic Epictetus’ account of the Cynic’s response to injustice.
Tolstoy
was more immediately influenced by the Stoics. He had in his library a
book about the Stoics, Epictetus and Marcus Aurelius and other Greek
moralists, and had marked a translation of Marcus Aurelius with numerous
underlinings. One of Tolstoy’s remarks in The Kingdom of God is Within You
is reminiscent of Epictetus on freedom as an inviolability of the
rightly directed will, when he says: ‘It is impossible for a man to be
placed against his will in a situation repugnant to his conscience.’
Gandhi’s own remark in 1926 seems to echo this when he says: ‘No power
on Earth can make a person do a thing against his will.’ In both views,
the will cannot be forced, although Epictetus had said this only of the
rightly directed will. Gandhi’s comment is presumably not meant to deny
that one can act reluctantly, as in his example above, in which
non-violence is seen as even worse than violent action.
As early as 1909, Gandhi wrote about freedom in Hind Swaraj, translated into English as Indian Home Rule
(1910). Anyone who wants to engage in his resistance movement for the
service of the country has to observe perfect chastity, adopt poverty,
follow truth, and cultivate fearlessness, he wrote. Chastity is the
greatest discipline, and is necessary for the requisite firmness; it
excludes not marriage, but sexual relations within marriage. This meant
that, as with Epictetus’ free agent, Gandhi felt that he had nothing to
lose when the British put him in prison. When he faced imprisonment or
death through voluntary fasting in prison, it was the British who were
afraid. Gandhi wrote that this inner freedom was a prerequisite for home
rule, and was the real self-rule (swaraj), as he had also said even earlier in 1908 in his loose paraphrase and comment on John Ruskin’s Unto This Last (1860),
about the worker who arrived late getting the same wages as those who
arrived on time. Real self-rule, Gandhi argued, consists of restraint,
and requires a moral life, not cheating, not forsaking the truth, doing
one’s duty to parents, wife, children, servants and neighbour. Without
such reforms, the departure of the British from India would not supply
the country with true self-rule.
Gandhi published his Discourses on the Gita from February to November 1926. He then wrote a Gujarati translation of the Bhagavad Gita
in 1927, and a Gujarati introduction to it in 1929, and an English
translation just of the introduction after that. His secretary Desai
translated Gandhi’s Gujarati translation into English, with a learned
commentary, and this was published after Desai’s death as The Bhagavad Gita According to Gandhi
(1946). Some of the verses advocate an attitude of detachment or
detached indifference to opposite outcomes in life, although only one
English verse uses the word ‘indifferent’, and it is always the person
who is indifferent to opposite outcomes, not, as with the Stoics, the
outcomes that are called indifferent. Detachment, as opposed to
attachment, might therefore be the clearer description, and indeed the Gita repeatedly requires action without attachment, including attachment to the fruits of action. It could well be from the Gita that Gandhi absorbed analogues to the Stoic theory of the indifference of outcomes and the importance of good character.
Gandhi was interested in another quite different kind of freedom, moksha,
in the traditional Indian sense of escape from rebirth, which is also
discussed by Plato. He said he would like to escape after this life, or
after one more rebirth, but if he was to be reborn, he would like to be
reborn as one of the group then called ‘untouchables’, now Dalits
or the oppressed, to share their sorrows and endeavour to free himself
and them. It has been pointed out that this contrasts with the more
common route to escaping rebirth by retreat from the world. Instead,
Gandhi found a glimpse of God in being among the suffering millions. At
one point, he also said that the truest self-rule, the path of moral
restraint in the world, was synonymous with moksha,
although self-rule is not so obviously connected with escape from the
world. But it has been pointed out that self-rule too would once have
been seen as requiring retreat from the world of rule by princely
rulers, whereas for Gandhi self-rule involved, as we saw above, a moral
life, involving one’s duties to others.
The
philosophical themes central to Gandhi – non-violence and freedom – are
full of surprises. His thinking is never conventional. But there are
surprises in other themes too. Gandhi said to the English writer H G
Wells that he would prefer a Charter of the Duties of Man to a Charter
of the Rights of Man. This would have appealed to the Stoics, who
thought character alone to be very important, but the ordinary needs of
life to be merely preferred indifferents. That seems to suggest that if
the just man or woman had acted to meet others’ needs but, through no
fault of theirs, the intended needs were not met, the important thing
would nonetheless have happened. Gandhi’s reason was different: talk of
rights tends to lead to violence. He still connected rights with duties,
but in a quite unexpected way. The point familiar to us is the
linguistic one, that if I have rights, that very claim implies that some
others will have duties not to interfere with them. Gandhi
makes instead a point that is not linguistic, but rather a substantive
value judgment: I will have no rights over my family, unless I first
perform my duties towards them.
Gandhi’s political actions were
also full of surprises. To illustrate them, I must return to the
relation between his philosophy and his politics.
Perhaps the most
famous political surprise was Gandhi’s Salt March of 1930. The British
had put a high tax on salt. This was lucrative because everyone needs
salt, and so it put a burden on Indians of all faiths, but the heaviest
burden was on the poor for whom it was hardest to pay. On 2 March 1930,
Gandhi sent a private and courteous letter with a list of 11 steep
demands to the British Viceroy, including, among others, the abolition
of the salt tax, and said that he would engage in civil disobedience if
they were not met.
The letter was not made public for at least a
week. Being refused, Gandhi prepared a march and announced on 5 March
that the cause would be the salt tax. He chose non-violent marchers who
would not resist assault nor even death, if attacked. The precautions in
his instructions of how to remain non-violent, and his advance
provisions for arrival in villages on the route, were a model of
foresight and planning. The destination, on the Surat coast, was not
announced until 9 March. The 240-mile march through villages began on 12
March, gaining Indian and international attention, and arriving 24 days
later in Dandi on the coast on 5 April. Gandhi bathed in the sea and
scooped up salt with his fingers from the natural salt deposits, without
having paid tax, thereby breaking the law.
It is not opportunism that Gandhi sometimes allows violence yet often forbids it too
From
there on, the salt-tax law and others were openly violated throughout
India. Gandhi was arrested on 5 May before a second salt march, while
still writing a letter to the Viceroy to forewarn him of it. At that
second act of civil disobedience, iron-tipped staves were brought down
on the skulls of unresisting protesters, who fell to the ground,
although only four were reported to have died in that period. Gandhi was
taken to Poona (now Pune) jail. Released on 26 January 1931, he thanked
his jailers for their care and said that he felt he was leaving peace
and quiet. The new confidence of the resistance movement took almost
everybody by surprise, although it would be more than 16 years before
India became independent.
I have already given an example to show
why I think Gandhi’s philosophy needs to be studied if his politics are
to be understood. It is not opportunism that he sometimes allows
violence yet often forbids it too. His belief is subtle (and, to my
mind, correct) that, although violence is always wrong, it does not give
us exceptionless laws of how to act. As already mentioned, he did not
think of himself as a philosopher. But neither, for that matter, did he
care for politics, which he once called a ‘botheration’, even though he
was a great tactician. He put politics below spiritual values, and would
give up political objectives if they clashed with spiritual ones.
Nonetheless,
his conclusions about non-violence were to have an enormous impact on
India, and not only there. It was partly because he had won worldwide
admiration that Britain, weakened by the Second World War, had no choice
but to leave India. By the count of Gene Sharp, founder of the Albert
Einstein Institution, which is dedicated to advancing the study of
non-violent action, there have been 23 non-violent resistance movements
influenced by Gandhi in the 20th century and beyond, up to 2005; Martin
Luther King, Jr’s was only one. Some have used Sharp’s analysis of
Gandhi’s techniques as a handbook. Sharp regards about half of these
resistance movements as having succeeded. I think one further effect of
Gandhi’s non-violent approach was that there was so little bitterness
among first-generation Indians towards the British once they had left,
although later generations could well be much more upset when they read
the history of British occupation.
Gandhi’s politics were not
always so successful. The Dalits complained that he failed to support
their leader B R Ambedkar on the plight of ‘untouchability’, as it was
called. Gandhi himself realised that he could not prevent the massacres
involved in the Partition of India in 1947 into India and Pakistan, when
people did not know until the last moment where the boundary would be,
and whether they would have to lose their family homes through being on
the wrong side of the border. With the massacres, Gandhi lost his
earlier wish to live to 123 years of age. But his ability to surprise
never left him. When the British asked him to quell the pre-Partition
massacres in Calcutta (Kolkata), he came and converted one of the
massacre’s leaders to non-violence. When the Indian National Congress
(which was due to rule India but which he had left) asked Gandhi how to
persuade Muhammad Ali Jinnah to give up his project of founding
Pakistan, Gandhi replied: ‘Offer him the prime ministership of a united
India, and swear to support the decisions of the cabinet that he
chooses.’
To read Gandhi, then, is to read a great spiritualist
who inspired new ideals across the world – and a great tactician. But my
point has been that it is also to read someone who provides a model for
philosophical thinking.
No comments:
Post a Comment