We owe all living creatures an obligation to be kind because the negation reflects on our own ability to improve morally or eliminate karma. Yet that is where it ends.
Arguments against animal husbandry are self negating. After all, without us, all cattle, all chickens and all domesticated anything would be simply extinct. All of us live in order to die and that includes the whole web of life.
The spirit body which is apparently eternal or the next best thing supports the whole life web. Better it supports large numbers at the same time. Thus when you pluck a dandelion, it is appropriate to thank the king of the dandelions for his gift. The same applies for all creatures.
Even we share a number of aspects for each life cycle we enter into. I am told that the number is around thirty. We even get to choose life experiences beforehand.
Thus saying death is wrong is a false argument and entirely misses the whole point of life..
.
A ‘humanely’ killed animal is still killed – and that’s wrong
Western conventional wisdom about animal ethics is that killing an
animal is not the problem; the problem is making the animal suffer. As
long as we have treated and killed an animal in a ‘humane’ way, we have
done nothing wrong. A compelling example of this belief is found in the
case of dogs and cats, animals particularly valued in Western culture.
If someone inflicts suffering on a dog or cat, they are excoriated. But
unwanted dogs and cats are routinely ‘put to sleep’ – killed – in
shelters with an intravenous injection of sodium pentobarbital, and most
people do not object as long as the process is administered properly by
a trained person and there is no suffering inflicted on the animal.
Why do we think that killing animals per se is not morally wrong? Why do we think that death is not a harm for non-human animals?
Before the 19th century, animals were mostly regarded as things. Neither our use nor our treatment of them mattered morally or legally. We could have obligations that concerned animals, such as an obligation not to damage our neighbour’s cow, but that obligation was owed to our neighbour as the owner of the cow, not to the cow.
To say that we thought of animals as things didn’t mean that we denied that they were sentient, or subjectively aware, and had interests in not experiencing pain, suffering or distress. But we believed that we could ignore those interests because animals were our inferiors. We could reason; they couldn’t. We could use symbolic communication; they couldn’t.
Why do we think that killing animals per se is not morally wrong? Why do we think that death is not a harm for non-human animals?
Before the 19th century, animals were mostly regarded as things. Neither our use nor our treatment of them mattered morally or legally. We could have obligations that concerned animals, such as an obligation not to damage our neighbour’s cow, but that obligation was owed to our neighbour as the owner of the cow, not to the cow.
To say that we thought of animals as things didn’t mean that we denied that they were sentient, or subjectively aware, and had interests in not experiencing pain, suffering or distress. But we believed that we could ignore those interests because animals were our inferiors. We could reason; they couldn’t. We could use symbolic communication; they couldn’t.
In
the 19th century, a paradigm shift occurred, and the animal welfare
theory was born. In a relatively brief period of time as far as major
shifts in thinking go, we claimed to reject the notion of animals as
things, and to embrace the idea that animals had moral value. Prominent
in this paradigm shift was the lawyer/philosopher Jeremy Bentham, who
argued in 1789 that, although a full-grown horse or dog is more rational
and more able to communicate than a human infant, ‘the question is not,
Can they reason? nor, Can they talk? but, Can they suffer?’
Bentham
maintained that the fact that animals were cognitively different from
humans – that they had different sorts of minds – did not mean that
their suffering did not matter morally. He argued that we could no more
morally justify ignoring the suffering of animals based on their species
than we could ignore the suffering of slaves based on their skin
colour.
But Bentham did not advocate that we stop using animals as
resources in the manner he had advocated abolition in the case of human
slavery. He maintained that it was morally acceptable to use and kill
animals for human purposes as long as we treated them well. According to
Bentham, animals live in the present and are not aware of what they
lose when we take their lives. If we kill and eat them, ‘we are the
better for it, and they are never the worse. They have none of those
long-protracted anticipations of future misery which we have.’ Bentham
maintained that we actually do animals a favour by killing them, as long
as we do so in a relatively painless manner: ‘The death they suffer in
our hands commonly is, and always may be, a speedier, and by that means a
less painful one, than that which would await them in the inevitable
course of nature … [W]e should be the worse for their living, and they
are never the worse for being dead.’ In other words, the cow does not
care that we kill and eat her; she cares only about how we treat and kill her, and her only interest is not to suffer.
And
that is precisely what most of us believe today. Killing animals is not
the problem. The problem is making them suffer. If we provide a
reasonably pleasant life and a relatively painless death, we have done
nothing wrong. Interestingly, Bentham’s views are endorsed by Peter
Singer, who bases the position he articulates in Animal Liberation
(1975) squarely on Bentham. Singer claims that ‘the absence of some
form of mental continuity’ makes it difficult to understand why killing
an animal is not ‘made good by the creation of a new animal who will
lead an equally pleasant life’.
We think that this view is wrong.
To say that a sentient being – any
sentient being – is not harmed by death is decidedly odd. Sentience is
not a characteristic that has evolved to serve as an end in itself.
Rather, it is a trait that allows the beings who have it to identify
situations that are harmful and that threaten survival. Sentience is a means to the end of continued existence.
Sentient beings, by virtue of their being sentient, have an interest in
remaining alive; that is, they prefer, want or desire to remain alive.
Continued existence is in their interest. Therefore, to say that a
sentient being is not harmed by death denies that the being has the very
interest that sentience serves to perpetuate. It would be analogous to
saying that a being with eyes does not have an interest in continuing to
see or is not harmed by being made blind. Animals in traps will chew
their paws or limbs off and thereby inflict excruciating suffering on
themselves in order to continue to live.
Singer recognises that
‘an animal may struggle against a threat to its life’, but he concludes
that this does not mean that the animal has the mental continuity
required for a sense of self. This position begs the question, however,
in that it assumes that the only way that an animal can be self-aware is
to have the sort of autobiographical sense of self that we associate
with normal adult humans. That is certainly one way of being self-aware,
but it is not the only way. As the biologist Donald Griffin, one of the
most important cognitive ethologists of the 20th century, noted,
it is arbitrary to deny animals some sort of self-awareness given that
animals who are perceptually conscious must be aware of their own bodies
and actions, and must see them as different from the bodies and actions
of other animals.
Even if animals live in the ‘eternal
present’ that Bentham and Singer think they inhabit, that does not mean
that they are not self-aware or that they do not have an interest in
continued existence. Animals would still be aware of themselves in each
instant of time and have an interest in perpetuating that awareness;
they would have an interest in getting to the next second of
consciousness. Humans who have a particular form of amnesia might be
unable to recall memories or engage in ideation about the future, but
that does not mean that they are not self-aware in each moment, or that
the cessation of that awareness would not be a harm.
It is time
that we rethink this issue. If we saw killing an animal – however
painlessly – as raising a moral issue, perhaps that might lead us to
start thinking more of whether animal use is morally justifiable, rather than only whether treatment
is ‘humane’. Given that animals are property, and we generally protect
animal interests only to the extent that it is cost-effective, it is a
fantasy to think that ‘humane’ treatment is an attainable standard in
any case. So if we take animal interests seriously, we really cannot
avoid thinking about the morality of use totally apart from
considerations of treatment.
No comments:
Post a Comment